How do Science and Religion Relate?

             For centuries, the highest figure in human culture and society was the resident religious head.  The Jewish high priests of antiquity, the Catholic Popes and the oracles of ancient Greece were all held in the highest esteem.  Even the Pharaohs of ancient Egypt were considered to be high priests of the gods.  If a great problem arose in society, everyone would look to their religious leaders for a solution.   As such, theology went unquestioned as the highest possible avenue of study. 

                This all changed with the advent of modern science.  Men and women in lab coats are now the popular experts on any number of academic and intellectual issues.  Yet, religion continues on in a very prominent way.  Very few of the six or so billion people on earth would consider themselves atheists.  So how do we, who revere science, understand our religion in light of the secular academy?  And how do we practice our secular sciences in light of our religious beliefs?  It seems that a model is needed to help us relate the disciplines of science and religion.  In this paper, four such models will be offered.  One of these models will be supported, defended and illustrated using two separate test cases.

Barbour’s Four Models

                Historically, there have been a variety of ways by which people have attempted to relate science and theology. Ian Barbour categorizes these attempts into four broad models: Conflict, Independence, Dialogue and Integration.[1] 

                The conflict model holds that science and theology are consistently at odds with one another.  Either science is being impeded by religious belief, or religion is being besieged by atheistic science.  Some hold this position because they believe religion holds back honest scientific inquiry.  Evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins has been quoted as saying, “I am against religion because it teaches us to be satisfied with not understanding the world.”[2]  Others point to the lack of a moral compass in science to show that it is in conflict with moral religion.  Atrocities committed in the name of scientific progress are often cited.  Religious peoples favoring the conflict model often cite the Nazi regime of the 1940s.  Historian Richard Evans reports the gruesome experiments carried out on Jews in the Nazi concentration camps but writes that the Nazis saw these as necessary for the advancement of science. “German medical science had uncovered the causes of several major diseases and contributed massively to improving the health of the population over the previous decades. Surely, therefore, it was justified in eliminating negative influences as well?”[3]  The conflict model is also the most popular model today.  For example, the trial of Galileo under the Catholic Church for proposing a heliocentric universe is taught to students of all ages.  It seems natural, then, to assume science and religion are in constant conflict with one another.

                Others have held that science and religion merely address mutually exclusive truth claims.  This is known as the independence model.  Stephen Jay Gould’s principle of non-overlapping magisterial, or NOMA, is a popular example of this model.  While Gould believes both science and religion are equally important and necessary in human life, “they remain logically distinct and fully separate in style of inquiry, however much and however tightly we must integrate the insights of both magisteria to build the rich and full view of life traditionally designated as wisdom.”[4]  Within such a model, if either science or religion appears to be in conflict, it is because one or the other has overstepped its boundary.  While both address objective truth claims, they cannot both address the same aspect of reality at the same time and in the same meaning. 

                Barbour’s third model is the dialogue model.  As the name suggests, this model encourages the idea that science and religion can engage in discussions and learn from each other.  They may ask where one discipline begins and the other ends, or they may share methodological schemes as in when one tries to apply empirical tests in the world of theology. 

The fourth of Barbour’s models is integration.  Examples of this model can include when one tries to infer the existence of God from natural sources, when scientific theories are integrated into one’s theological understanding, or when one arrives at a comprehensive understanding of reality that includes both scientific and theological truths.  Garry DeWeese uses the term “Convergence” for this model, as he believes that science and theology should retain their disciplinary integrity.[5]  This is the model that I favor and the model that the remainder of this paper will endeavor to support. 

Against Scientism

                Those that ascribe to the conflict model or the independence model often hold to a strong or weak view of scientism, views that the integration model rejects.  Strong scientism is the view that science defines rationality and is the only method by which one can discern truth.  If something cannot be known by scientific investigation, then it is not true or rational.  Weak scientism, which is more popular, holds that truths of a non-scientific nature may exist and that they may have some status of rationality.  However, scientific rationality and truths have authority and have more value than any other form of inquiry.  While someone may have their own thoughts about the mind, the authoritative view is that the mind is best explained via neurophysiology and psychology.  If either strong or weak scientism is true, then a convergence model of science and religion cannot be correct.  However, if we can show that strong scientism and weak scientism are deficient views, then we can show that aspects of the conflict, independence and versions of the dialogue models are left wanting.   For if science is not the only method, or even the strongest method for arriving at truth, then it must be supplemented by other avenues of inquiry and rationality.  I propose that theology, within a convergence model, should be and is one of those avenues.

                Strong scientism, as the more severe of the scientism positions, is relatively easy to dismiss.  First, it is self-refuting.  The statement that “science is the only legitimate foundation to find truth” is not itself a scientifically verifiable statement.  It is a philosophical statement about science.  Moreover, there are several other non-scientific presuppositions that allow science to be practiced.  The laws of logic and mathematics, for example, cannot be proven scientifically.  Yet they are foundational to the scientific enterprise. Since these problems are easily seen and difficult to ignore, most who favor scientism have adopted weak scientism.

                Yet weak scientism is not without faults.  First, along with strong scientism, weak scientism has a difficult time allowing for the philosophical presuppositions that are foundational for the practice of science.  J.P. Moreland and William Lane Craig provide a list of several scientific presuppositions that are merely assumed aside from the aforementioned laws of logic and mathematics.  They include the existence of a theory-independent world, the orderly nature of the external world, the knowablility of the external world, the existence of truth, the uniformity of nature and the ability to trust induction as a method to find truth.[6]  Since these presuppositions are not scientific, weak scientism would have us believe that they are somehow less authoritative than scientific statements.  Yet these scientific statements would not exist if not for the non-scientific foundational truths that were previously assumed.  It seems to follow then that the presuppositional truths must be assumed to be just as authoritative if not more so than the generated scientific truths.

                Second, neither form of scientism adequately allows for the existence of true and rationally held beliefs outside of science.  Moral truths and self-evidential truths serve as examples.  Moreover, many of these truths seem to have better justification than many truth claims believed within science.  One cannot prove scientifically that rape is wrong, but most people hold this to be true.  Moreover, they hold this to be true and have more justification than the theory of Darwinian evolution.   A further problem for scientism that parallels its inability to allow for these truths is that scientific truths have changed repeatedly throughout history while many truths outside of science have remained consistent.  The objective truth that murder is wrong has persisted over many different cultures and centuries.  The scientific truths regarding the placement of the earth in the universe has changed dramatically and repeatedly over the same time span.  Moreland and Craig write, “It is not hard to believe that many of our currently held scientific beliefs will and should be revised or abandoned in one hundred years, but it would be hard to see how the same could be said of the extrascientific propositions.”[7]

                Thus we can confidently conclude that science cannot be the only source, nor even the most important source, of truth.  Many truths about philosophy, morality and theology seem to be more foundational and more objective than many scientific truths we accept today.  Moreover, some of these truths provide the very foundation on which science functions, thus rendering the conflict and independence models insufficient.  What is often overlooked is that the philosophical idea of naturalism functions as a sort of religion for many scientists.  Regarding science’s implicit religious doctrines, Van Till writes, “What often confuses the issue… is the fact that this particular ‘religion’ of naturalism is so commonly embedded in works that are presented to readers as being no more than popularizations of modern science.”[8]  Furthermore, the dialogue model, which supposes a distinction between scientific knowledge and non-scientific knowledge, fails to recognize the role that non-scientific truth claims play in all scientific inquiry.  We are thus left with the integration model of relating science and religion.   However, we are not left with integration merely as a process of elimination.  Integration has its own strengths which strengthen its claim as the appropriate means to relate science and religion.  We will now turn to how one may approach the integration of theological claims with scientific claims.

Application of Integration

                While I favor DeWeese’s use of the term “Convergence,” I will continue to utilize Barbour’s term of integration for continuity’s sake.  However, the idea of convergence does seem to more appropriately capture the idea that there is one collective and objective truth that both science and religion are attempting to describe.  Indeed, the existence of such an objective truth is something that both science and religion recognize regardless of which model one ascribes to.  Furthermore, science and religion are both tools that purportedly exist to find and describe objective truth.  As such, they have a common goal.  If one has the goal of constructing a skyscraper, it makes little sense to utilize different tools in a conflicting or independent way.  Instead, one would utilize cranes, bulldozers, dump trucks and excavators in an integrative way.  As we have seen, religious truths and scientific truths are integrated in a complex and complete unity of objective truth.  Therefore, we must investigate this truth with tools that are equally integrated.

                It is one thing to recognize the need for integration.  It is another to describe how one might apply such a model.  In some cases, integration causes no controversy as it is not necessarily applied.  The scientific fact that every macroscopic physical action causes an equal and opposite reaction does not seem to carry much theological weight.  Likewise, the theological claim that Abraham’s trust in God was credited to him as righteousness appears to have no bearing in the scientific realm.  In such cases, there appears to be no overlap between religious truth and scientific truth.  While they both point to the same objective reality, there is no chance for conflict or active integration.

                In cases of overlap, there may either be mutual strengthening or conflict.  In the case of strengthening, scientific evidence may directly support religious claims or vice versa.  The current scientific model of the Big Bang supports the Biblical claim that the universe had a beginning when God created it.  Likewise, many theological teachings encourage the study of the natural world in order to gain a deeper understanding of reality.  Such overlap offers explicit support for the integration model.

                However, conflict often arises when theological and scientific claims overlap.  While the aforementioned Big Bang theory does offer support to the Christian theological doctrine of creation, it also seems to contradict a young earth interpretation of the Genesis narrative.  The scientific theory of Darwinian Evolution is at odds with varying version of theological creationism.  Human stem cell research clashes with deeply held theological convictions regarding the human soul and personhood.  In order for the integration model to be successful, it must first show that it can successfully handle such conflicts.

                According to the integration model being proposed, both science and religion are attempting to explain the same external reality.  It follows then that if science and religion are claiming two mutually incompatible things about this external reality that one or both are incorrect in their claims.  This does not mean that science or religion is illegitimate as a method of arriving at objective truth.  Rather, it means that both enterprises are carried out by people who make mistakes.  Thus, when conflict arises within the integration model, one should look at one’s science or theology for flaws.  This must be done on a case by case basis.  While in one case one’s theological reasoning may be flawed and thus in conflict with science, in another case it might be one’s scientific reasoning that may be flawed.  But it if is to be done on a case by case basis, on what criteria is it to be judged?  DeWeese and others have offered several questions to ask in order to direct our adjudication,[9] and I offer several of them here.

                First, assuming that an actual contradiction is at hand, one should first look to see if either the scientific or the theological claims are axiomatic within their discipline.  For example, if one’s scientific claims contradict one’s Christian claim to the deity of Christ, then one must first look for errors within one’s scientific claims.  Otherwise, one’s Christian theology would be utterly destroyed.  Similarly, science necessitates the human ability to observe the external world as it is.  If one’s theology teaches that demons actively and continually distort our perception of reality, then this would strike at the core of scientific inquiry and one’s theological beliefs ought to be suspect.

                Second, one must consider the amount of independent support for conflicting theological and scientific claims.  One scientific experiment does not warrant the repudiation of a hundred clear theological teachings.  Nor do one or two obscure Scriptural texts render a well-established scientific theory null and void.  For example, a cursory reading of Genesis might lead one to believe that there was no pain or suffering among the animals before the creation of Adam.  However, an in depth fossil record shows ample evidence that carnivorous animals existed long before mankind.  Since the Bible is largely silent on the issue of pre-fall animal suffering, and since the scriptures that apparently speak to this are few and less than explicit, one should not discredit the fossil record evidence based on theological reasons.

                Third, one should take care to make sure that neither the scientific claims nor the theological claims suffer from significant internal problems.  Internal logical contradictions, such as those mentioned in strong scientism above, render any claims to be fallacious.  But there are other lesser types of internal problems.  New archaeological finds may render one’s interpretation of historical theology questionable.  A new scientific discovery may call into question long standing scientific theories.  Such internal problems need not discredit a claim made by science or theology, but they may weaken them.  Thus, if these weakened claims come into conflict with an opposing scientific or theological claim, their weakened status should be further considered.

                Fourth, one may wish to suspend judgement altogether if a decision is not forced and if neither the theological evidence nor the scientific evidence is strong enough to persuade a reconsideration of the other.  This is typically the case when the two claims are not central to the truth claims made by either side.  For example, one might believe the Pharaoh described in the book of Exodus to be Ramses I instead of Amenhotep II or Thutmose II.  However, all have historical evidences in their favor and none is conclusive.  Therefore, it is advisable to suspend judgement in the absence of further historical evidence.        

Objections to Integration

                Before we move on to case studies involving our proposed integration model, we should first briefly discuss a couple objections that have been raised against it.  First, it has been argued that by integrating religion into science, we have introduced a “god-of-the-gaps” mentality in which god is merely inserted into areas which science has not yet spoken to.  This is then used as an apologetic by theists much like the natural theologians of years past.  Furthermore, it is argued that since science is increasingly filling these gaps, this is really just a slow weening off of religion altogether. 

                This is clearly just a reassertion of weak scientism that assumes that scientific knowledge is superior to any and all religious knowledge.  There are several replies that may be offered in turn.  First, there is nothing in the integration model which limit’s the activity of a deity.  If one were to adopt a Christian perspective, it is clear that God is sovereign of all of nature and continually upholds it.  As such, he upholds science as well.  Moreover, there need not be any apologetic aim within the integration model at all.  Moreland and Craig write, “A Christian theist may simply believe that he or she should consult all we know or have reason to believe is true – including theological beliefs – in forming, evaluation and testing scientific theories and in explaining scientific phenomena.”[10]

                Second, the integration model does not seek to insert theology only when science is lacking.  Certain theological truths are more central and should be expected to play a more pivotal role in nature.  The falleness of man and nature should be expected to manifest itself in natural pain and suffering.  One should have theologically expected the universe to have had a beginning even before the Big Bang became a popular theory. 

                Third, while it may be true that scientific theories are covering more ground and the gaps are getting smaller, it does not follow that there will eventually be no gaps at all.  Indeed, biogenesis and cosmogenesis are two examples of phenomena that are doubtful to ever be explained by science.  If God acts in a primary way via miracles, gaps should be expected.  Moreover, rarity is an attribute of miraculous events.  This means that most of God’s actions are through secondary causes, which are able to be investigated via science.  God’s actions through primary causes are thus all the more obvious because they are so rare.

                Finally, one needs to differentiate between historical science and empirical science when discussing a “god-of-the-gaps” theology.  Empirical science is carried out within a laboratory setting and is based on repeatable, regularly occurring events.  As such, it is immune from talk of the miraculous.  However, historical science focuses on past events which are not repeatable.  It is thus legitimate to discuss God’s primary causal activity in the historical sciences while it is not in the empirical sciences.  If something is not yet explainable by science in the empirical sense, it ought to remain an open question instead of a hasty assertion of the miraculous.

                The second objection to the integration model is similar to the sentiment posed by Richard Dawkins earlier in this paper, namely that religion stifles scientific inquiry.  It is argued that God’s primary causal activity is not fruitful in guiding new research or yielding testable results.  Therefore, an appeal to God’s direct causation cannot be an acceptable scientific practice.  Regarding this idea, Richard Dickerson writes, “The most insidious evil of supernatural creationism is that it stifles curiosity and therefore blunts the intellect.”[11]

                In response, one might first point out that something can be true without being fruitful in guiding new inquiry.  If God truly did create the universe out of nothing via a Big Bang like process, this would be a onetime occurrence that would never be repeatable.   Thus, further research in the specific area of “creation ex nihilo” would be impossible.  Yet, while further research in this area would be halted, it would not necessarily entail the fallaciousness of the creation claim, especially if the claim were made for good theological and scientific reasons.  Secondly, even if one were to grant that theological concepts have not yet generated new lines of inquiry, it does not follow that such lines of inquiry would not be developed in the future.  Lastly, it may be that in a theological framework a certain phenomenon may be considered basic while in a naturalistic framework it is not and vice versa.  This will clearly have implications on further inquiry into the phenomenon for the different frameworks. 

Case Studies for Integration

                Now that we have briefly defended the integration model against objections, it is time we look at case studies.  I will look at two separate case studies that exemplify different capabilities of the integration model.  The first example will showcase how the model may offer mutual enrichment for both science and religion in areas that are not necessarily fiercely debated, but could be problematic.  The second example will show how the integration model can deal with a historically contentious issue where science and religion appear to be in outright conflict.

                Our first example will be the so-called problem of the applicability of mathematics.  Most, if not all of science is based on the language of mathematics.  Quantum physics is almost entirely explained using mathematical equations.  Yet, we have very little philosophical reason (and no scientific reason) to expect the abstract world of mathematics to interact this way with the physical world.  Einstein once asked, “How is it possible that mathematics, a product of human thought that is independent of experience, fits so excellently the objects of physical reality?”[12]

                Historically, there have been two views on this problem, neither of which necessitates a Christian or theistic worldview, and both of which have flaws as solutions.  The first is the platonic or realist view of mathematics.  This view holds that mathematics exists as an objective reality outside of the natural world.  Oxford mathematical physicist Roger Penrose says, “Mathematical truth is not determined arbitrarily by the rules of some ‘man-made’ formal system, but has an absolute nature, and lies beyond any such system of specifiable rules.”[13] As such, mathematics is unchanging and outside of the human mind.  It can thus be harvested to explain things that do occur in the natural realm.  The shortcoming of this view is that it does not offer an explanation as to why or how the external mathematical realm has any active or passive influence whatsoever on the physical world.

                Of course, an objective non-physical mathematical world does not fit into the philosophical naturalism that many practitioners of modern science adopt.  As such, many have come to adopt an anti-realist view of mathematics.  The Einstein quote above hints at how anti-realists view mathematics.  They believe that it is a purely human construct.  Since man is the direct result of natural selection acting upon random variation, mathematics is likewise a product of evolution.  It is easy to see how an individual who “puts two and two together” in an appropriate way has a survival edge over one who does not.  As a survival tool, math became genetically ingrained into the human brain.  According to such a naturalist perspective, math has no existence outside of the human brain.  Furthermore, since humanity has supposedly evolved from one or very few common ancestors, this genetically imbedded mathematics is common to all humanity.  Thus, mathematics merely appears universal. 

                The naturalistic problem is that the anti-realist position sheds no light on the applicability problem.  The math required for most scientific application is superbly complex.  It is in no way clear that such abstract and complex mathematics was at any point beneficial for the survival of the human species.  Furthermore, if our mathematics is subjective to the human race, then the science based on that math is also subjective.  In other words, if we were to contact another intelligent race in the universe, they might have an entirely different system of logic, math and physical sciences.  This runs contrary to the very claim of naturalism that science is “true” in some objective sense. 

                However, if one were to view the applicability problem within an integration model, the problem may be solved almost immediately.  We may first look at the internal problems within the anti-realist position and favor the platonic position.  Next, we see that the problem with the platonic position (that it is not obvious how the mathematical realm interacts with the physical) is easily solvable once an intelligent deity is allowed to be the conduit for which mathematics is consistently applied to the physical world.  Christian mathematician John Byl writes, “Within the context of Christianity it makes sense to talk about the objective existence of numbers and mathematical truths.  Once God is removed, there is nowhere to place abstract mathematical concepts and nobody to guarantee their truthfulness.”[14]  By integrating one’s religious ideas with the realm of scientific application, one is left with a mutually enriched perspective which allows for the applicability of mathematics in and objective and fruitful way.

            A second test case in which conflict can be resolved using the integration model is that of the evolution-creation debate. It can be safely assumed that the reader is well aware of the conflict between naturalistic Darwinian evolution and the Judeo-Christian view of creation.  The Darwinian side claims that it is based on science and reason.  The Judeo-Christian side claims to have divine revelation in its favor.  How does the integration model here presented handle this situation?

            First, we should look to see if the conflict impinges upon foundational or axiomatic claims on either side. It seems that it does in both cases.   On the Darwinian side, the claim that God miraculously created life impinges upon the foundational scientific assumption of uniformitarianism.  Moreover, it contradicts the naturalistic assumptions of many Darwinists.  Conversely, this naturalism is directly contradictory to the claim that God is actively involved in creation and contradicts the doctrine of God as creator and sustainer of all things.

            Thus, we must look at independent support for each side.  It seems that there is ample evidence for God as creator from other fields such as philosophy, cosmology, ethics and logic.  Meanwhile, there is little support for naturalism as a position other than a mere axiomatic assertion.  However, there is ample evidence within the fossil record that shows a slow progression of ever more complicated biological lifeforms over the past billion years. This lends support to the general idea of evolution, but not necessarily to a naturalistic form of the theory.

            Third, we shall consider if either side has significant internal problems.  Here we see some headway in our integration model, for the naturalistic assumptions behind Darwinian evolution are seen to be fatally flawed.  Within naturalism, there is a deeply ingrained belief in scientism.  As we have seen, scientism is deeply flawed.  Moreover, Darwinian evolution has no answer as to how life began to exist.  Conversely, if one were to adopt a young earth creationism, there appears to be ample physical evidence that supports an old earth fostering millions of years of biological change.  If, however, one adopts an old-earth reading of Genesis, these internal conflicts decrease dramatically.

            Lastly, we may entertain the idea of suspending judgement.  While this is certainly possible in this case, I do not think it is necessary.  I believe once naturalism has been removed from the theory of Darwinian evolution and the idea of God as creator and sustainer of the process has been included, the previous conflict has been greatly reduced if not eliminated. 

Conclusion

            We can therefore conclude that the integration model is preferable over the conflict, independence and dialogue models.  After one rejects a strong or weak form of scientism, the integration model rises to the top as the model of choice.  The application of the application model can be approached methodically and thoughtfully so as to not explicitly favor either science or religion uniformly in all cases.  Objections against integration are generally offshoots of scientism and naturalism and can sufficiently answered.  Finally, we saw that the integration model can be used to mutually enrich both science and religion as well as resolving apparent conflicts between the fields.









[1] Ian G. Barbour, Religion and Science: Historical and Contemporary Issues (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1997), pp. 77-105.
[2]Michael Ruse, Science and Spirituality: Making Room for Faith in the Age of Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), p. 3.  Ruse attributes this quote to RichardDawkins.net, quote 49.
[3] Richard Evans, “How Hitler Perverted the Course of Science,” The Telegraph. December 1st, 2008. Web. Accessed December 12th, 2016.
[4] Stephen Jay Gould, Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the Fullness of Life, (New York, NY: Ballantine Books, 1999),  p. 59.
[5] Garry DeWeese, “Understanding Nature,” Doing Philosophy, March 22nd, 2011. p. 291.
[6] J.P. Moreland & William Lane Craig, Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview, (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2003). p.248.
[7] Moreland & Craig, p. 350.
[8] Howard Van Till, “Partnership: Science and Christian Theology as Partners in Theorizing,” Science and Christianity: Four Views, (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2000). p. 201.
[9] DeWeese, pp. 292-293.
[10] Moreland & Craig, p. 363.
[11] Richard Dickerson, “The Game of Science: Reflections After Arguing with Some Rather Overwrought People,” Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith. 44 (June 1992). P. 137.
[12] Max Jammer, Einstein and Religion, Princeton University Press, 1921.
[13] Roger Penrose, Shadows of the Mind, Searching for the Missing Science of Consciousness (Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, 1994). P. 418.
[14]John Byl, The Divine Challenge: On Matter, Mind, Math & Meaning. (Carlisle, PA: Banner of Truth,2004). p. 255.